HAROLD SCHAD, Jr.,
PETITIONER v. ARIZONA
[June 21, 1991]
The common law recognized no degrees
of murder; all unlawful killing with malice aforethought received the
same punishment — death. See F. Wharton, Law of Homicide 147 (3d ed.
1907); Moreland, supra, at 199. The rigor of this rule led to
widespread dissatisfaction in this country. See McGautha v.
California, 402 U.S. 183, 198 (1971). In 1794, Pennsylvania divided
common-law murder into two offenses, defining the crimes thus:
"[A]ll murder which shall be
perpetrated by means of poison, or lying in wait, or by any other kind
of willful, deliberate, or premeditated killing; or which shall be
committed in the perpetration, or attempt to perpetrate any arson, rape,
robbery, or burglary, shall be deemed murder of the first degree; and
all other kinds of murder shall be deemed murder in the second degree."
1794 Pa. Laws, ch. 1766, 2.
That statute was widely copied, and
down to the present time the United States and most States have a single
crime of first-degree murder that can be committed by killing in the
course of a robbery as well as premeditated killing. See, e. g.,
18 U.S.C. 1111; Cal. Penal Code Ann. 189 (West 1988 and Supp. 1991); Kan.
Stat. Ann. 21.3401 (Supp. 1990); Mich. Comp. Laws Ann. 750.316 (1991);
Neb. Rev. Stat. 28-303 (1989).
[n.1]
It is Arizona's variant of the 1794 Pennsylvania statute under which
Schad was convicted in 1985 and which he challenges today.
Schad and the dissenting Justices
would in effect have us abolish the crime of first-degree murder and
declare that the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment requires
the subdivision of that crime into (at least) premeditated murder and
felony murder. The plurality rejects that course — correctly, but not in
my view for the correct reason.
As the plurality observes, it has
long been the general rule that when a single crime can be committed in
various ways, jurors need not agree upon the mode of commission. See,
e. g., People v. Sullivan, 173 N. Y. 122, 65 N. E. 989
(1903); cf. H. Joyce, Indictments 561-562, pp. 654-657 (2d ed. 1924); W.
Clark, Criminal Procedure 99-103, pp. 322-330 (2d. ed. 1918); 1 J.
Bishop, Criminal Procedure 434-438, pp. 261-265 (2d. ed. 1872). That
rule is not only constitutional, it is probably indispensable in a
system that requires a unanimous jury verdict to convict. When a woman's
charred body has been found in a burned house, and there is ample
evidence that the defendant set out to kill her, it would be absurd to
set him free because six jurors believe he strangled her to death (and
caused the fire accidentally in his hasty escape), while six others
believe he left her unconscious and set the fire to kill her. While that
seems perfectly obvious, it is also true, as the plurality points out,
see ante, at 7, that one can conceive of novel "umbrella" crimes
(a felony consisting of either robbery or failure to file a tax return)
where permitting a 6-6 verdict would seem contrary to due process.
The issue before us is whether the
present crime falls into the former or the latter category. The
plurality makes heavy weather of this issue, because it starts from the
proposition that "neither the antiquity of a practice nor the fact of
steadfast legislative and judicial adherence to it through the centuries
insulates it from constitutional attack," ante, at 15 (internal
quotations omitted). That is true enough with respect to some
constitutional attacks, but not, in my view, with respect to attacks
under either the procedural component, see Pacific Mutual Life
Insurance Co. v. Haslip, 499 U. S. —, — (1991) (slip op., at
15) (Scalia, J., concurring in judgment), or the so-called
"substantive" component, see Michael H. v. Gerald D., 491
U.S. 110, 121-130 (1989) (plurality opinion), of the Due Process Clause.
It is precisely the historical practices that define what is "due."
"Fundamental fairness" analysis may appropriately be applied to
departures from traditional American conceptions of due process; but
when judges test their individual notions of "fairness" against an
American tradition that is deep and broad and continuing, it is not the
tradition that is on trial, but the judges.
And that is the case here.
Submitting killing in the course of a robbery and premeditated killing
to the jury under a single charge is not some novel composite that can
be subjected to the indignity of "fundamental fairness" review. It was
the norm when this country was founded, was the norm when the Fourteenth
Amendment was adopted in 1868, and remains the norm today. Unless we are
here to invent a Constitution rather than enforce one, it is impossible
that a practice as old as the common law and still in existence in the
vast majority of States does not provide that process which is "due."
If I did not believe that, I might
well be with the dissenters in this case. Certainly the plurality
provides no satisfactory explanation of why (apart from the endorsement
of history) it is permissible to combine in one count killing in the
course of robbery and killing by premeditation. The only point it makes
is that the depravity of mind required for the two may be considered
morally equivalent. Ante, at 17-19. But the petitioner here does
not complain about lack of moral equivalence: he complains that, as far
as we know, only six jurors believed he was participating in a
robbery, and only six believed he intended to kill. Perhaps moral
equivalence is a necessary condition for allowing such a verdict
to stand, but surely the plurality does not pretend that it is
sufficient. (We would not permit, for example, an indictment
charging that the defendant assaulted either X on Tuesday or Y on
Wednesday, despite the "moral equivalence" of those two acts.) Thus, the
plurality approves the Arizona practice in the present case because it
meets one of the conditions for constitutional validity. It does
not say what the other conditions are, or why the Arizona
practice meets them. With respect, I do not think this delivers the "critical
examination," ante, at 17, which the plurality promises as a
substitute for reliance upon historical practice. In fact, I think its
analysis ultimately relies upon nothing but historical practice (whence
does it derive even the "moral equivalence" requirement?) — but to
acknowledge that reality would be to acknowledge a rational limitation
upon our power, which bob-tailed "critical examination" obviously is not.
"Th[e] requirement of [due process] is met if the trial is had according
to the settled course of judicial proceedings. Due process of law is
process due according to the law of the land." Walker v.
Sauvinet, 92 U.S. 90, 93 (1876) (citation omitted).
With respect to the second claim
asserted by petitioner, I agree with Justice Souter's analysis,
and join Part III of his opinion. For these reasons, I would affirm the
judgment of the Supreme Court of Arizona.
*****
Notes
|