SCHAD
v.
ARIZONA
certiorari to the supreme court of arizona
No.
90-5551.
Argued
February 27, 1991
— Decided June 21, 1991
Held: The judgment is
affirmed.
163 Ariz. 411, 788 P. 2d 1162,
affirmed.
Justice Souter delivered the
opinion of the Court with respect to Part III, concluding that Beck
v. Alabama, 447 U.S. 625 — which held unconstitutional a state
statute prohibiting lesser included offense instructions in capital
cases — did not entitle Schad to a jury instruction on robbery. Beck
was based on the concern that a jury convinced that the defendant
had committed some violent crime but not convinced that he was guilty of
a capital offense might nonetheless vote for a capital conviction if the
only alternative was to set him free with no punishment at all. See
id., at 629, 630, 632, 634, 637, 642-643, and n. 19. This concern
simply is not implicated here, since the jury was given the "third
option" of finding Schad guilty of a lesser included noncapital offense,
second-degree murder. It would be irrational to assume that the
jury chose capital murder rather than second-degree murder as its means
of keeping a robber off the streets, and, thus, the trial court's choice
of instructions sufficed to ensure the verdict's reliability. Pp. 19-22.
Justice Souter, joined by
The Chief Justice, Justice O'Connor, and Justice Kennedy,
concluded in Part II that Arizona's characterization of first-degree
murder as a single crime as to which a jury need not agree on one of the
alternative statutory theories of premeditated or felony murder is not
unconstitutional. Pp. 4-19.
(a) The relevant enquiry is not, as
Schad argues, whether the Constitution requires a unanimous jury in
state capital cases. Rather, the real question here is whether it was
constitutionally acceptable to permit the jury to reach one verdict
based on any combination of the alternative findings. Pp. 4-5.
(b) The long-established rule that a
jury need not agree on which overt act, among several, was the means by
which a crime was committed, provides a useful analogy.
Nevertheless, the Due Process Clause does place limits on a State's
capacity to define different states of mind as merely alternative means
of committing a single offense; there is a point at which differences
between those means become so important that they may not reasonably be
viewed as alternatives to a common end, but must be treated as
differentiating between what the Constitution requires to be treated as
separate offenses subject to separate jury findings. Pp. 5-11.
(c) It is impossible to lay down any
single test for determining when two means are so disparate as to
exemplify two inherently separate offenses. Instead, the concept of due
process, with its demands for fundamental fairness and for the
rationality that is an essential component of that fairness, must serve
as the measurement of the level of definitional and verdict specificity
permitted by the Constitution. P. 11.
(d) The relevant enquiry must be
undertaken with a threshold presumption of legislative competence.
Decisions about what facts are material and what are immaterial, or, in
terms of In re Winship, 397 U.S. 358, 364, what "fact[s] [are]
necessary to constitute the crime," and therefore must be proved
individually, and what facts are mere means, represent value choices
more appropriately made in the first instance by a legislature than by a
court. There is support for such restraint in this Court's "burden-shifting"
cases, which have made clear, in a slightly different context, that the
States must be permitted a degree of flexibility in determining what
facts are necessary to constitute a particular offense within the
meaning of Winship. See, e. g., Patterson v. New York,
432 U.S. 197, 201-202, 210. Pp. 11-13.
(e) In translating the due process
demands for fairness and rationality into concrete judgments about the
adequacy of legislative determinations, courts should look both to
history and widely shared state practice as guides to fundamental values.
See, e. g., id., at 202. Thus it is significant here that
Arizona's equation of the mental states of premeditated and felony
murder as a species of the blameworthy state of mind required to prove a
single offense of first-degree murder finds substantial historical and
contemporary echoes. See, e. g., People v. Sullivan, 173
N. Y. 122, 127, 65 N. E. 989, 989-990; State v. Buckman,
237 Neb. 936, — N. W. 2d —. Pp. 13-17.
(f) Whether or not everyone would
agree that the mental state that precipitates death in the course of
robbery is the moral equivalent of premeditation, it is clear that such
equivalence could reasonably be found. See Tison v. Arizona,
481 U.S. 137, 157-158. This is enough to rule out the argument that a
moral disparity bars treating the two mental states as alternative means
to satisfy the mental element of a single offense. Pp. 17-18.
(g) Although the foregoing
considerations may not exhaust the universe of those potentially
relevant, they are sufficiently persuasive that the jury's options in
this case did not fall beyond the constitutional bounds of fundamental
fairness and rationality. P. 19.
Justice Scalia would reach
the same result as the plurality with respect to Schad's verdict-specificity
claim, but for a different reason. It has long been the general rule
that when a single crime can be committed in various ways, jurors need
not agree upon the mode of commission. As the plurality observes, one
can conceive of novel "umbrella" crimes that could not, consistent with
due process, be submitted to a jury on disparate theories. But first-degree
murder, which has in its basic form existed in our legal system for
centuries, does not fall into that category. Such a traditional crime,
and a traditional mode of submitting it to the jury, do not need to pass
this Court's "fundamental fairness" analysis; and the plurality provides
no persuasive justification other than history in any event. Pp. 1-5.
Souter, J., announced the
judgment of the Court and delivered the opinion of the Court with
respect to Part III, in which Rehnquist, C. J., and O'Connor,
Scalia, and Kennedy, JJ., joined, and an opinion with respect
to Parts I and II, in which Rehnquist, C. J., and O'Connor
and Kennedy, JJ., joined. Scalia, J., filed an opinion
concurring in part and concurring in the judgment. White, J.,
filed a dissenting opinion, in which Marshall, Blackmun, and
Stevens, JJ., joined. |